In 1985 out of the State University of Montana an economic professor had the right idea.

An idea before its time. It is now 2010 twenty-five years latter, and the  time is now. The time is now to start the path diligently and with true applied force to end all taxation one venue at a time?

The precedents  are well in place as of 2010 for  theft  of the  population's wealth and productivity value. Done systematically with our government being run by attorneys exercising corporate precision in the perpetuation of easy money on a massive scale for the benefit of the inside track.


They entertain the population with the seriousness of the current circumstances and planed distraction as they chuckle behind closed doors as and while the massive stacks of cash changes hands under their control, at their discretion; and primarily done so perpetuating their own empire building large and small both domestic
and internationally. .

Mr. Edwards writings are  not  for  the entertainment  of the Simpson's  mentality.  It  is geared for the intelligent and educated mind  having  the ability  for comprehensive cognitive thinking. His writing is in depth  with references given. Please share with your friends that have business backgrounds and also with you local government officials and educators.


Sent FYI from,


Walter Burien - CAFR1


To automatically subscribe to CAFR1 NATIONAL posts -  http://CAFR1.com/phplist/?p=subscribe




Mr. Edwards is an associate professor of economics at Montana State University-Northern.


FINANCING GOVERNMENT WITHOUT TAXATION

by James Rolph Edwards
"Winter of 1985"

Upon occasion  it is worthwhile to consider the boundaries of the possible. Men of limited imagination construe them narrowly and indeed,  for such people they are narrow. One  hears most frequently (and dogmatically) of the  impossibility of  financing government without taxation  from those who have  never seriously  considered the problem.  The  possible,  however, varies  directly  with  the  amount  of intelligence  applied, and there are good reasons  for considering this issue. 

Reflection upon the  malevolent  inclinations of some individuals and the necessity for a
single set of laws in a given area has caused even  most  libertarians to conclude that government  is a necessary institution, without which civilization would be impossible. But it  is also a dangerous and  malignant  institution. As such  its legitimate functions  must be rigorously defined, then specified  in  a constitution which  limits government to those functions, and provides institutional checks on the concentration  and growth of government power. 

Proceeding  from rationalist-individualist philosophy, libertarians  have developed the clearest and  most consistent criteria ever  devised  for  distinguishing  the  legitimate  from  the  illegitimate functions of government. The argument proceeds as follows: First, no one has the right to initiate the use of force against anyone else, though each  individual  has the right  to its defensive  and retaliatory uses. Second,  the state gets all of  its authority  from  its citizens, and they cannot grant to government rights they do not have. Hence government is  simply the  institutional repository of the defensive and retaliatory uses of force. It protects people from each other and from outsiders so that  they  must interact  on a voluntary, contractual  basis.  All redistributive programs, morality  legislation, price controls  and so on are ruled out
a priori.1

Despite  being  far superior to any comparable theory of governmental  function, even this scheme displays apparent flaws. For one, it seems to make no provision for the allocation of property rights, which  is at  least in part a government  function, necessary  in order to reduce externalities so that  the  market can allocate resources efficiently.  This  problem  is  more  apparent  than  real,  however.  The notions of the illegitimacy of force and fraud, and of the legitimacy of contract  (and  of  governmental  enforcement  of  contract)  all  rest  upon the presupposed existence and  legitimacy of property. People who have the right to own and transfer property, and even acquire it through the appropriation of previously  unowned resources, have the right to vest government with the authority to register and protect such property, as well as to codify the rules  for  its  legitimate acquisition. These powers do
not involve the initiation of coercion. 

A more serious objection derives  from the supposed necessity of taxation to support even the minimal state. If true, the contradiction is profound. How can the state, which gains  its  legitimate authority from the rights of individuals, which do
not include the right to initiate coercion, finance itself through taxation, which is inherently coercive? More than one critic of libertarian thought has dismissed it on this basis. Libertarians themselves have been split on the issue, some (the anarcapitalists) choosing to believe that the state can be abolished, and others (the minarchists) choosing to suffer the contradiction for the sake of the minimal state.2 Oddly enough, even the number of libertarians who have seriously attempted to conceive of methods of financing the state without taxation is small. 

It may be less difficult to devise such a scheme than many people assume. Consider the current situation in which the U.S. government is taxing and spending at very high levels. Now suppose political conditions allow a reduction in the budget and elimination of extraneous programs such that government was spending money only on its legitimate functions. Suppose, moreover, that it continued taxing at current levels and deposited the surplus.
The government could continue depositing its surplus revenue each year until the interest on its deposits became large enough to entirely finance its annual expenditures, at which point all taxation could be eliminated. Indeed, the power to tax or borrow money could be eliminated. 

Put another way, what the government would be doing in running a surplus is operating with a positive cash balance, rather than a negative cash balance (debt). It is often argued in opposition to proposals for balanced budgets, that the government
must be allowed to run deficits and borrow money in order to be "able" to match fluctuating revenue and expenditure flows. A sillier argument is difficult to imagine. Fluctuating revenue and expenditure flows can be matched just as easily by drawing a positive cash balance up or down when required, as by adjusting debt.3 

The benefits of financing the federal government from interest on its cash balance would be enormous and would begin with the first surplus. When the government runs a negative cash balance, borrowing money to finance a deficit, it raises interest rates and "crowds out" private borrowers. Consider a graph in which D
p and Sp represent the private demand for and supply of credit, and i is the resulting market rate of interest. Cp is the dollar value (in billions) of credit purchased by the public, in order to finance the purchase of capital goods and durable consumer goods, including housing. 
Cp

Now assume that the government enters the credit market as a borrower in order to finance a deficit, raising demand to Dp+g the sum of private and governmental demand. The  interest rate  rises to i', reducing the quantity of credit demanded by private parties to Cp'. The difference between Cp and Cp'  is private housing, other durable goods and  capital investment lost due  to governmental  borrowing. This  has had detrimental  long term effects  in reducing U.S. growth rates and employment.


If instead of running a deficit the government ran a surplus, the supply curve in the credit market would shift from S to S
p+g'', lowering  the interest rate to i'' and increasing private credit purchased to C p''. The housing and (non-housing) durable goods  markets would  expand immediately, and the  additional  capital  investment would raise the growth rate of American production over time. Unemployment would fall  and  jobs would  be created  for  those who lost welfare payments with the elimination of such programs. 

If government were constrained to living off the  interest  from its deposits as suggested here,  it would  face greatly  increasing incentives to  operate efficiently. The only  way  it could  increase  its budget without drawing down  its principal (which would allow increased present expenditure, but only at the cost  of reduced  future expenditure) would be by spending less  than  its  annual  earnings  and allowing a portion of  its  interest to compound. In order to spend  less than its earnings, it would be necessary to keep costs down by finding cheaper  and  more  efficient  methods  of  operation.  In  essence government would be brought into the market and  forced to calculate costs almost like a  business, though  it would  retain  its  legitimate legislative, judicial, diplomatic and enforcement powers.5 

The political economy of inflation would also be altered under such  a  system.  Strong  incentives  currently  exist  for  the  federal government  to finance at  least part  of  its negative cash balance  by selling  bonds to  the Federal  Reserve, which  increases the rate of growth in the money stock and adds to the rate of inflation. First, this allows partial escape  from the crowding-out problem. Second, since the real rate of  interest is the nominal rate minus the rate of  inflation, raising  the  latter  term  allows  the  government  to  covertly  repudiate much  of  the  national  debt  (though  this  works  only  until  creditors' expectations of  future  inflation rates adjust and the nominal rate  is raised enough to restore  the real rate, as  finally happened  in 1981). Third, inflation raises revenue through bracket creep.
6

Forcing government to live on the revenue  from  its deposits would eliminate all of these  incentives  for monetary expansion. Also, under the political conditions supposed, the present temptation  for government to use  inflation  in an attempt to reduce unemployment caused by labor legislation, minimum wage laws, and social programs, would no longer  exist.  In fact, it might be necessary  to remove from government the power  to control the money  stock to prevent  it from
deflating in an attempt to raise the real value of its interest revenue. Of course much of the benefit of this system would ultimately come from the elimination of taxes itself. Taxes alter relative prices, and hence disturb the efficient allocation of resources.7 The effect of the present progressive  tax  structure  in  motivating  significant  substitution  of leisure for labor and current consumption for investment at the margin is particularly pernicious.  All  such effects would disappear with the elimination of taxes, resulting  in greater economic growth and more efficient allocation of resources. Of  course  many of these  benefits could  and  should  be  obtained  before the complete elimination of taxation  by  appropriate  reform,  say  by  the  substitution  of  a  flat-rate income tax or a value added tax for the present system. 

II

There are, of course, certain potential objections to the scheme proposed here which come to mind. It might even be claimed to violate the  libertarian theory  from which  it proceeds. Anarcapitalists  in particular will deny that coercive taxation is justified even for a limited period. Even minarchists may object to taxation rates exceeding those required for the finance of legitimate governmental functions over such a period.8  Three responses are in order. 

First, it is precisely from recognition of the objectionable nature of taxation that the proposal made here for its
elimination flows. Until and  unless  some  other  feasible  method  of  financing  government without taxation is developed, the real alternative is not the absence of taxation, but perpetual taxation. Surely that is not preferable to taxation for a period that is specifically designed to be self-terminating. 

Second,  the degree of coercion  involved  in taxation  is  not related to the
rate of taxation, but is related directly to its coverage and inversely to its support. Clearly the majority of the  voting population currently support taxation.9 It is not they who are being coerced, but a dissenting minority which includes some subset of libertarians. Might not even this minority  be severely reduced  if  its  members know that current tax revenues were being used to obtain the eventual elimination of taxation? If so, the scheme proposed would immediately reduce the degree and extent of coercion in the system. 

Third, the extended taxation would  not be associated with reduced  income (from the 
loss of the potential  gains from  reduced  taxation)  on  the  part  of  taxpayers  except  for  a  short  period.  The specific use made of the surplus revenues under the scheme proposed would in fact  result in increased  real  after-tax  incomes  available  to people  for their discretionary use due to  the  productivity growth already  discussed.  It  is  very  difficult  to  see  a  loss,  then,  from  the temporary continuance of taxation at rates greater than required to fund current functions. 

This also provides the answer to another potential objection. The proposed scheme  may  be argued to involve an unjust intergenerational wealth transfer, since the present generation  is taxed so  that  future  generations  may  go  untaxed.  But  the  real  situation  is quite different since the present generation would gain due to the use made of the revenues. Nor is  it clear that  they  would gain  less than future generations. The efficiency of the economy would  increase  with  the  elimination  of  taxation,  but  the  growth  of  the financial and physical capital pool would slow at that point. What the intergenerational effects would be are not obvious. All that is obvious is that both the present and future generations would gain

Some libertarians might object that large portions of the annual surpluses would  be used to purchase  stocks (and bonds) rather than simply deposited, resulting in government ownership and/or control of a great many firms. This scheme could be argued, in other words, to be a back-door form of socialism. In the absence of the power  to subsidize, however, it is difficult to see how the character or operations of such firms would be altered. They would still be market institutions subject to competitive discipline, and
all of their stockholders would be interested  in their efficient operation. Besides,  if some  legitimate objection to government stock purchases were discovered such purchases could be prohibited by a clause in the legislation creating the system. 

Keynesian economists will object to the program set forth here by arguing that the consequence of the surpluses proposed would be an enormous decrease  in aggregate demand, severely reducing employment and output.
10 However, in the absence of any alteration in  the  monetary  growth  rate, there  is  no reason to suppose that deficits or surpluses add to or detract from total  spending  in the slightest.  Every dollar government adds  to spending  in covering a deficit,  for example,  is simply a dollar  lost to private consumption or investment  spending  on  the  part  of  the11 bondholder from whom  the government borrowed the money. 

In the case of a  surplus the option  faced by the government  is whether to pay
off  bondholders or deposit  the  funds. However this decision is made there will be a dollar added to private consumption or investment spending  for each dollar of reduced government expenditure.12 Aggregate money  expenditure will not change, though this does  not mean the economy will  not be affected. What  the proposed  surpluses  would  do  is  redirect  spending  from  socialist programs which simply circulate money and discourage production to investments  in physical capital  and durable goods which  increase production. 

The possibility of paying  bond  holders raises the  issue of the existing national debt, which has not yet been mentioned. Certainly the legitimate governmental expenditures would  have to be defined to include payments on the debt. In 1980 and 1981  federal  interest payments were running about 12 percent of receipts. This has risen, but it is still less than 20 percent. Thus it should be possible to make such payments 
along with  expenditure on the other  justifiable  functions of government and  still run a  healthy surplus.  With the  elimination of continued  federal  borrowing the existing debt would be gradually retired  as  outstanding  bonds  matured.  It  is  true,  however,  that  the necessity for debt service increases the length of time required for the federal deposits to raise  its  interest  revenue to  the  level of  its annual outlays. 

Perhaps the most serious problem may lie in which economists term the elasticity of demand,  in particular, of the capital (or credit) demand curve. Government revenue from its deposits (and  investment) base and the market rate of interest, a problem might arise as  to  the  growth  of  the  deposit  base  caused  by  the  interest  rate  to decline. If a point were reached at which the demand curve was elastic, that  is  the  percentage decline  in  the  interest  rate  exceeding  the percentage increase in  the base, interest  revenue  would begin  to
decline

The question, then,  is whether the (net) revenue curve would peak at a level large enough to finance justified annual expenditures. If it did not, upon the elimination of taxes (which should be specified in the initial law  to  occur 
either when revenue  covers expenditures or when revenue starts falling) some other non-coercive  means or obtaining revenue would  have to be applied to cover residual expenditures.  Examples might include voluntary  contributions, lotteries, Federal land sales, or user fees.13 

The probability is, however, that the problem would not arise. For  one  thing, international financial markets  are highly  integrated, which means that the capital supply curve is elastic for anyone country in the  system.  As a result,  interest rate movements are somewhat restricted. For another,  the economic growth stimulated by the  lower interest  rate  'Would  tend  to  shift both  the  capital demand  and  supply curves out. The net effect would almost certainly be an elastic response to revenue from the deposits. 


The existence of  international capital market  integration raises another point. The presence of  significant externalities  in a  market 'Will  prevent  efficient  resource  use.
14 It could be argued that such an externality exists and would operate in the case supposed. It is true that the  fiscal policy advocated and the consequent fall  in  interest rates would probably result  in  significant capital exportation. If so, a good deal of physical capital and productivity growth would therefore occur outside the United States. 

If this  financial and physical  capital transfer went uncompensated, an  externality  could  be said to occur, and domestic financial capital accumulation could  be said to  be excessive,  but a closer  look  shows  it  would  not.  Domestic  investments  in  foreign countries  'Would earn returns, and dollars accumulated  in  foreign balances  'Would  sooner or  later be used to purchase domestic goods and services. The  international accounts  must balance. The capital account deficit would be matched by a current account
surplus, just as, currently, our account deficit resulting  from  federal  borrowing  is matched  by  a capital account surplus.15 Clearly  no externality  is involved. 

The
least serious objection to the idea proposed here is that it is politically  unfeasible. There was a time when a  largely  market directed,  limited government society  'Was thought to be utopian, and its  institutionalization  'Was politically unfeasible. Nevertheless the conditions arose for the emergence of such a society, and did so to no small extent as a consequence  of education and  political struggle by those who conceived the benefits of such institutions.  As Mises put it: 

Any  existing  state  of  social  affairs  is  the  product  of ideologies previously thought out. Within society new  ideologies may emerge and may supersede older ideologies and thus transform the social system. However, society is always the creation of ideologies temporally and logically anterior. Action is always directed by ideas; it realizes what previous thinking has designed
.16 
 
III

Some evidence on the economic feasibility of the proposed institutional innovation may be indicated by the experience of Hong Kong. Hong Kong is one of the few remaining British crown colonies, and has never had an indigenous democratic government. As such it has faced relatively little pressure for imposition of welfare state practices. In fact its administrators have, in contradistinction, followed a highly laissez-faire policy. This policy has resulted in very rapid output and real income growth, despite extremely limited physical resources and a population density which is not only large, but increasing, due to refugee immigration as well as internal growth.17 

There are several factors behind this growing prosperity. The government has largely restricted itself to maintaining order, and tax rates have been kept very low. The presence of a large amount of cheap labor, kept cheap by inexpensive food imports -- attributable to a policy of complete free trade -- and by a near absence of labor legislation (until recently), has meant a high rate of return to entrepreneurs. This high rate of return, in combination with the political conditions in communist China, has resulted in expatriate Chinese throughout Asia investing large amounts of capital in Hong Kong.
18 

A less noticed factor in Hong Kong's growth is that, despite its low tax rates, the government has systematically run budget surpluses for several decades.
19 Infrequent deficits have occurred but have been easy to cover from the accumulated surplus revenue.20 It has been recently reported that the annual interest on these cumulative deposits is sufficient to cover nearly 40 percent of annual government expenditures. What is more, this proportion could clearly be increased rather rapidly, since, despite its laissez-faire character, the Hong Kong government is engaged in a number of semi-socialistic enterprises and interventionist pursuits which could be easily eliminated from the budget.2l 

Economic phenomena are intrinsically complex, and with so many factors favoring economic growth in Hong Kong, it would be extremely difficult to disentangle the effect of the budget surpluses from those of the capital importation, low tax rates, paucity of regulation, free trade, etc., even were the required data available.
22 Statistical study of the issue therefore remains a matter for future research, though a priori the effect is positive, and there certainly seems little evidence of the contractionary effect postulated by the Keynesians. 

Some will object, as they already have, that the historical and institutional situation of Hong Kong is unique and not applicable elsewhere.
23 But the very fact that a nation has been able to practice such policies, with such undeniably beneficial results, casts doubt on the nation that they could not be practiced  elsewhere, particularly in the United States, which has history of limited government and a philosophy of laissez-faire.24 If Hong Kong can restrict government activities and run budget surpluses until the interest earned is capable of covering a major portion of its annual expenditures, then why could not this policy be extended to cover 100 percent of such expenditures? And if Hong Kong could do this, why not the home of the brave and the land of the free? 
 
NOTES AND REFERENCES
 
1) See Ayn Rand, "Appendix: The Nature of Government," in Capitalism, the Unknown Ideal (New York: Signet Books, 1967): 330-331

2) The intellectual leader of the anarcapitalist wing of the libertarian movement is Murray Rothbard. See his For a New Liberty (New York: Macmillan, 1973), and his Power and Market Government and the Economy (Menlo Park, California: Institute for Humane studies, 1970). Leading minarchist libertarians include the late Ayn Rand and John Hospers. See his Libertarianism (Los Angeles: Nash Publishing Co., 1971): chapter 1. 

3) This is exactly the way the government of Hong Kong operates. See below.

4) It is quite possible for government to spend money in ways which increase the nation's capital stock, as, for example, when it builds dams and highways. But particularly given the shift in the composition of the budget towards income transfer programs in the last two decades, it is not doing so on net. 

5) A critic of an early draft of this paper made a valid point here by pointing out that it is not enough to insure efficiency that the maximum of funds available is fixed. There also has to be a fear that the minimum is not fixed. The critic then denied that endowed chairs in the academy were under tremendous pressure to operate efficiently. But surely: they are under more pressure, and do operate more efficiently that does government, to which neither the maximum nor the minimum is fixed under the current structure. 

6) Subject to the limits of the Laffer Curve, of course.

7) This is admitted even by liberal economists. See William Baumol and Alan Blinder, Economics: Principles and Policy (New York: Harcourt Brace Javanovich, 1982): 561-568.

8)  This is not speculation. Both of these objections and the "intergenerational transfer" objection discussed below were explicitly made by the critic mentioned in note 5 above. 

9) We may wish this were not so, but it clearly is, and will continue to be the case until the public is convinced that some practical, non-coercive, alternative means of governmental finance is available. 

10) The reasoning here is that taxation reduces disposable income and therefore reduces consumer spending, so this reduction must be offset by government spending if a contraction in total spending is to be avoided. See Paul Samuelson, Economics (l0th edition, New York: McGraw-Hill, 1976): 288. For the fallacy in this reasoning, see below. 

11) See Norman B. Ture, "Supply Side Analysis and Public Policy," in David G. Raboy, ed., Essays in Supply Side Economics (Washington D.C.: The Institute for  Research on the Economics of Taxation, 1982): 13-16. 

12) The same reasoning applies whether the surplus results from a reduction in government spending, as supposed here, or from an increase in taxation. In the latter case, however, the increased private consumption and investment spending
attributable to the deposits and debt payments would offset reduced private consumption and investment due to the increased taxation. 

13) As an example in the latter category, the government might be allowed to operate the Interstate highway system on a toll basis, sharing the net revenue with the states in a proportion determined by their original contributions to the construction costs. Competition from state roads would keep the tolls low, and users would pay the full cost of their driving, as they should. 

14) On the nature of the externality problem, see Steven N. S. Cheung, The Myth of Social Cost (London: Institute of Economic Affairs, 19m 2I-68.
 
I5) Martin Feldstein, William Niskanen and William Poole, "Annual Report of the Council of Economic Advisors," Economic Report of the President (Washington D.C.: U.S. Government Printing office: 1984): 42-57. 

16) Ludwig von Mises, Human Action (3rd revised ed., Chicago: Henry Regnery, 1963): 188. 

17) What is more, this rapid growth seems to have been associated with increasing, not decreasing, equality of incomes. See Steven C. Chow and Gustav F. Papanek, "Laissez-Faire, Growth and Equity --Hong Kong," Economic Journal 91 (June 1981): passim. 

18) Alvin Rabushka has written extensively on the economics, history, and economic history of Hong Kong. See his The Changing Face of Hong Kong (Washington D.C.: The American Enterprise Institute, 1973), and Hong Kong : A Study in Economic Freedom (Chicago: University of Chicago Press: l979). 

19) The government does not claim this is deliberate, but the pattern is clearly systematic. See The Changing Face of Hong Kong: 54-58, and Hong Kong: A Study in Economic Freedom: 51-55.

20) A public debt does exist, but it is extremely small. See The Changing Face of Hong Kong, 55. 

21) See above: 58-79. 

22) In accord with its laissez-faire policy, the government of Hong Kong did not even collect G.N.P. statistics until the mid-1970s. This led to much criticism from social scientists, of course.  See The Changing Face of  Hong Kong: 21-29. However, such information was never entirely missing.  Some statistical data can be found in the Hong Kong Annual Report, and the Hong Kong Monthly Digest of  Statistics

23) Rabuska flnd that the historical and institutional situation of Hong Kong is not unique. See Hong Kong: A Study in Economic Freedom: Chapter lV. 

27) Indeed, the United States has actually had extensive historical experience with budget surpluses. For over 150 years the U.S. basically followed a balanced budget policy. Wartime finances always resulted in heavy borrowing, but following a war
persistent surpluses would be run until the debt was either eliminated or greatly reduced. On this history see Richard Wagner, Robert Tollison et al., Balanced Budgets, Fiscal Responsibility and the Constitution
(Washington D.C.: the Cato Institute, 1982): It is also worth noting that at least two of these periods of extended post-war surpluses, those following the Civil War and World War ll, were notable periods of rapid growth and prosperity. 

------------------------------------------

BACK TO THE CAFR1 FRONT PAGE